This is Philosopher Fridays, a weekly(ish) series where I take a brief look at philosophers who’ve had an impact on my thinking, for good or ill. These posts are not meant to be comprehensive in any way, but instead are intended to provide a glimpse into an aspect of a thinker’s work that has stuck with me. For this post, while I have not drawn at all from any of my previous work, I have taken graduate course on Wittgenstein and the philosophy of language, and as such I owe my understanding of Wittgenstein to the guidance of my professors.
WITTGENSTEIN: Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein (1889 – 1951) was one of the most influential philosophers of the 20th century. Born in Austria, Wittgenstein spent most of his career in England teaching logic, mathematics, metaphysics, and language. One of the most interesting things to know about Wittgenstein’s biography, given recent conversations about Neil deGrasse Tyson, is that he wasn’t terribly invested in academic philosophy. He published very little, left the academy more than once, and actively discouraged students from going into not just philosophy, but any academic discipline. He had little faith that anyone would ever properly understand him, and pushed students instead toward more practical career paths.
Not that it stopped him from doing philosophy, of course. He was, according to Bertrand Russell, a genius, and though he was little published in his life, his notes, lectures, papers, and unfinished works have been made public after his death.
There are two points in Wittgenstein’s work that speak to me.
The first is from the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, which consists of seven main succinctly stated propositions about the self-evidence of logic and ontology, each with a series of subsets. They are as follows:
- The world is all that is the case.
- What is the case (a fact) is the existence of states of affairs.
- A logical picture of facts is a thought.
- A thought is a proposition with a sense.
- A proposition is a truth-function of elementary propositions. (An elementary proposition is a truth-function of itself.)
- The general form of a proposition is the general form of a truth function, which is:
. This is the general form of a proposition.
- What we cannot speak about we must pass over in silence.
While the entire work is intricate and fascinating, I find myself drawn most to propositions 6 and 7, particularly proposition 6.421:
It is clear that ethics cannot be put into words.
Ethics is transcendental.
(Ethics and aesthetics are one and the same.)
Which then leads, of course, to the silence required by things which fail to be captured by logical propositions.
Though some take this as a wholesale rejection of ethics and the mystical, I think it suggests a few more substantive things – it declares the impossibility of getting something factually “right” in the realm of ethics, but without completely dismissing the possibility that there might be some way to understand it, however alogical that understanding of principles would have to be. Here I’m stepping away from what Wittgenstein intended, perhaps, but I think it leaves room for exploring non-propositional, non-linguistically determinate ways of thinking about the transcendental.
The the second point of Wittgenstein’s work I’d like to highlight is from his posthumously published collection of Philosophical Investigations. Like the Tractatus, this work is not a cohesive work of narrative prose, but a series of almost aphoristic paragraphs. While there’s a lot of debate about “early” and “late” Wittgenstein, I think this quote makes for an interesting counterpoint to the proposition above.
And if we carry this comparison still further it is clear that the degree to which the sharp picture can resemble the blurred one depends on the latter’s degree of vagueness. For imagine having to sketch a sharply defined picture ‘corresponding’ to a blurred one. In the latter there is a blurred red rectangle: for it you put down a sharply defined one. Of course—several such sharply defined rectangles can be drawn to correspond to the indefinite one.—but if the colours in the original merge without a hint of any outline won’t it become a hopeless task to draw a sharp picture corresponding to the blurred one? Won’t you then have to say: ‘Here I might just as well draw a circle or heart as a rectangle, for all the colours merge. Anything—and nothing—is right.’—–And this is the position you are in if you look for definitions corresponding to our concepts in aesthetic or ethics (PI 77).
And if you’re taking this as a starting point (and not just aiming for Wittgensteinian discipleship) you can flip this around as well. Imagine that the Truth (real, capital T truth) is a rectangle. In order to provide demonstrative knowledge of this Truth, a philosopher has to figure out its exact dimensions and line their description up perfectly with reality. It can’t be off at all, or else it’ll miss the mark. There’s no “almost” involved in trying to line up two rectangles with precision. You’re either right, or you’re wrong. With the fuzzy version, it’ll overlap the precise reality of things easily, but it won’t give you a clear view – in fact it might even obscure it. Perhaps it’s better to think about the Truth as a fuzzy rectangle, and then try to find it with an even fuzzier one.
What I learn from this (and my reconstructed version) you’re much more likely to succeed with the fuzzy , but what you’ll get from it will be difficult to parse, and will have no determinate meaning. In terms of transcendental truths, like those of aesthetics or ethics, this once again opens up the possibility of thinking about what alogical understanding might entail.
I haven’t come to any conclusions, but it’s a thought I’m exploring in a number of different arenas – including this blog.
10 thoughts on “Philosopher Fridays: Wittgenstein”
whitefrozen
Interesting that Wittgenstein went from clearly and precisely stating what is the case to the painstaking gropings of the ‘Investigations’, in which he says almost nothing at all. He remains my favourite philosopher, in spite of his inability to say anything.
Michelle Joelle
That’s weirdly sort of the point, isn’t it?
whitefrozen
Perhaps. His discovery of depth-grammar seems to have stunned him in a way that he never recovered from, which is understandable.
Michelle Joelle
Perhaps we can see it in terms of PI77 – the Tractatus is his clear-edged rectangle, failing to adequately account for the fuzzier things, and the Investigations is his fuzzy-edge rectangle, performing its own obfuscation.
I’m just speculating, of course.
Witty Ludwig
I’m of the opinion that your phrasing here is slightly wide of the mark; that is, if you feel he said nothing at all in the PI. Even if less concise, which is precisely the point (which I presume is what Michelle alluded to in her immediate response), there is far more value to be found in the PI and it is precisely because of everything that is painstakingly said.
Steve Morris
Oh dear. I don’t understand any of that.
Michelle Joelle
Oh dear indeed! I’m sorry I wasn’t clearer – is there anything in particular maybe I can restate?
Steve Morris
Michelle, it wasn’t your fault. It’s just this whole Wittgenstein thing. I don’t understand a single one of his propositions, let alone how they relate to each other.
Thom Hickey
Thanks Michelle . W has such a powerfully attractive style and his writing opens up so much territory! I will investigate your blog further. Regards Thom at the immortal jukebox.
Michelle Joelle
Thanks Thom! I find Wittgenstein simultaneously delightful and maddening – what more could you want from a philosopher?